P. S. Greenspan “Guilt
and Virtue”
In his article title “Guilt and
Virtue” P.S. Greenspan seeks to displace guilt from the grips of ethics of
duty, or duty ethics (in his article Greenspan uses both terms
interchangeably). Briefly, ethics of duty “takes acts [or actions] as the
primary objects of moral evaluation” (Greenspan 57). In other words, human acts
or actions determine the degree of our morality. Greenspan sees this placement
of guilt within duty ethics as problematic and seeks instead to interpret guilt
through “virtue ethics” (Greenspan 57) and not duty ethics. The ethics of
virtue according to Greenspan “emphasizes the evaluation of persons and
personal traits in connection with notions of character” (57). Greenspan here
signals that acts should not be the sole factors in determining guilt, but that
guilt should be evaluated as a defining label of a person’s character and personal
traits. If an act is viewed as wrong “or a violation of moral obligation” then
according to duty ethics guilt should ensue after this particular act;
Greenspan seems to disagree with this theory and instead links guilt with
violations of one’s virtue, or “moral perfection” (Greenspan 57).
Greenspan sees guilt as a
“requirement of imperfect virtue”
(58), in other words, one cannot be both perfectly virtuous and guilty
simultaneously. Greenspan borrows this idea that one cannot be both virtuous
and guilty from Aristotle, who suggests that guilt or shame is not a virtue and
hence is a lapse from moral perfection (Greenspan 58). Then the question arises,
what does it mean to have virtue, or better yet, what defines a complete
virtuous person? Greenspan sees the answer in admiration: “[t]he question of
overall virtue…asks whether someone is an admirable person…on the whole, as opposed to being admirable only with some
qualification” (60). What Greenspan is
saying is that virtue is not quantifiable according to status or title, but
rather virtue is part of person’s character. A person cannot be virtuous simply
because he holds a respectable title that connotes virtue (such as President,
King, Senator, etc.) but rather virtue precedes a person’s title. Given this
situation we can see where problems start to arise given Aristotle’s theory of
virtue.
Virtue is not something that is
automatically acquired but rather is measured or “graded” (Greenspan 61)
according to a person’s sense of guilt and moral worth. Guilt does not diminish
a person’s sense of virtue or virtuousness but rather enhances it. Given that guilt requires a “heightened
sensitivity to one’s own moral wrongs” (Greenspan 61), guilt does not seem to
diminish a person’s moral worthiness. Virtue is not measured solely by actions,
but rather lies in a person’s sense of guilt and overall character. Given the
aforementioned definition of virtue, guilt then is “better in a way than
perfect virtue” (Greenspan 61) because it designates a person’s responsibility
for past wrongdoings and in doing so indicates a person’s awareness of their
own morality and moral faults. Therefore, the presence of guilt establishes the
presence of virtue (and not the lack thereof) since guilt is part of a person’s
character. This all connects to Greenspan’s idea of an “admirable person” (60) insofar as an “admirable person” has to feel guilt for his
actions in order to have virtue (based on virtue ethics and not duty ethics), an idea that we will
come back to in interpreting Crime and
Punishment and The Sense of an Ending.
Julian
Barnes The Sense of an Ending
The
Sense of an Ending by
Julian Barnes deals with guilt and remorse and what we decide to do with both.
In the novel, Tony is constantly battling over his guilt, and his relationships
seem volatile because of this. His sense of guilt and remorse, in my view,
comes from a misunderstanding of his experiences and the unreliability of his
memories. But what seems more important to Tony’s character is how he deals
with his guilt and remorse how this influences his acts/actions. And in my view this encapsulates his whole
character, and influences the actions he takes. He has a misunderstanding of
his past, and this turns into guilt, which then turns into anger, which then
turns into bad decisions, like sending the profanity laced letter to Adrian and
Veronica. Tony’s character will be interpreted according to Greenspan’s idea of
the “admirable person” (60) and his
guilt, acts/actions will be interpreted using Greenspan’s Ethics of Duty guilt
theory.
We
all make bad decisions, some that affect our life more than others, but it’s
impossible to change the past. When we try to change the past, which is an
impossibility, we are drowned with remorse. In the novel Tony the narrator
defines remorse as stronger than guilt and the feeling that occurs when you
come to the realization that the past is unchangeable. The bad decisions and
actions/acts that Tony makes are irreversible. Furthermore, remorse is the
feeling that enough time has passed that making amends or asking for
forgiveness would be ineffective. The problem with Tony is his remorse. Tony in
the novel does not understand nor grasp his guilt/remorse and does not
understand that his guilt/remorse might be misguided or beyond repair.
Take
for example his relationship with Veronica. This relationship seems to have
scarred him (no matter how short it lasted) for life and he even talks about
the circumstances of this relationship to his wife (when they were married). He
seems to want to grasp a complete and succinct understanding of this past
relationship, but what he experienced, remembers, and feels guilt for are all
completely different things. He seems to have guilt for breaking up with
Veronica and then sleeping with her, but this guilt does not necessarily mean
he has to act on it. We experience guilt every day, in my view, but we have to
choose our battles and sometimes the wiser choice is not to act on your guilt
and just live with it (with the memories and feelings).
Looking
back over the tragically insulting letter that he sent Adrian and Veronica in which
he stated that “it would be unjust to inflict in some innocent foetus the
prospect of discovering that it was the fruit of your loins” (Barnes 105), Tony
starts to feel a sentiment of regret and guilt. This was by far the stupidest
thing he could have done, and he certainly should feel guilt and even remorse
over it. He tries to wash away his guilt and responsibility by arguing that the
young snobbish Tony that wrote that letter is not the same Tony re-reading it
years later: “I didn’t recognize that part of myself from which the letter
came” (Barnes 107). Certainly the fifty-or sixty-something year old Tony is not
the same young Tony who wrote letter, but he is still culpable. I would argue
that he does recognize that young
self, but does not like his young self. In some way he is still the same, still
acting recklessly and deceiving himself.
So
the question arises: does Tony hold any virtue? Following Greenspan’s argument
one must have guilt in order to have virtue. Tony certainly has guilt, but what
does this say about his character? Greenspan states that one must have a “heightened
sensitivity to one’s own moral wrongs” (Greenspan 61) in order for a
sentiment/emotion to be defined as guilt. Tony definitely exhibits this sentiment
after re-reading his letter to Adrian and Veronica: “And so, for the first
time, I began to feel a more general remorse—a feeling somewhere between
self-pity and self-hatred—about my whole life” (Barnes 109). His sensitivity
towards his own wrongs is heightened to an extreme that it borders on
self-hatred. Tony’s guilt is overbearing and causes recklessness in his life.
But what is Tony to do with his guilt? He seems honestly apologetic to
Veronica, but of course the feeling is not mutual, and she responds with her
ever-clever remark: “’You just don’t get it, do you?’”(Barnes 110). Veronica
seems to insinuate that Tony does not understand the circumstances behind his
guilt. In other words, he seems detached from his guilt, and acts upon it
simply because he feels guilt but not because he understands the “why” behind
the guilt. He feels guilty because it is the morally right thing to do in order
to try to right his wrongs. But he still seems detached from the whole
experience. His actions are motivated by guilt, but is this enough to have
virtue?
If
we reject the theoretical trajectory behind Ethics of Duty, and instead
interpret Tony through the theoretical framework of Ethics of Virtue we can see
how Tony can be interpreted as a virtuous person and even an “admirable person”
(Greenspan 60). As mentioned earlier
Duty Ethics defines virtue primarily through the acts or actions that a person
takes, regardless of the person’s character or guilt. Duty Ethics leaves little
breathing room as far as moral evaluation is concerned. It seems that the moral
compass in Duty Ethics are acts/actions and nothing else. If an action violates
a person’s moral perfection then a person does not exhibit virtue, according to
the theory behind Ethics of Duty. In other words, once Tony starts feeling
guilty for the letter, he has already lost his virtue (according to Ethics of
Duty). The letter signifies the act/action that violated his moral perfection
and guilt signifies his “imperfect virtue” (Greenspan 58)
Through
an Ethics of Virtue lens Tony seems to exhibit the characteristics of a morally
upright person. He reveals guilt for his actions, but this guilt is part of a
larger “evaluation of […] personal traits in connection with notions of
character” (Greenspan 57). Virtue should
be evaluated as part of, or along with, a person overall character, and Tony
seems to agree:
Does character develop over time? In novels, of course it does:
otherwise there wouldn’t be much of a story. But in life? I sometimes wonder. Our
attitudes and opinions change, we develop new habits and eccentricities; but
that’s something different, more like decoration. Perhaps character resembles
intelligence, except that character peaks a little later: between twenty and
thirty, say. And after that, we’re just stuck with what we’ve got. We’re on our
own. If so, that would explain a lot of lives, wouldn’t it? And also—if this
isn’t too grand a word—our tragedy.
(Barnes 113)
In the above passage Tony is arguing that he
is not the same person, and does not hold the same character, as he did when he
wrote the letter. If guilt is part of his character now then his guilt should
be evaluated along with his other personal traits like love for his daughter
and his family. an “admirable person”
(Greenspan 60) has to feel guilt for his actions in order to have virtue (based
on virtue ethics), then Tony’s guilt can be evaluated as evidence of his
virtue. Given that his guilt is evidence if his virtue then we can safely
conclude that Tony is an “admirable person” given that “[t]he question of
overall virtue…asks whether someone is an admirable person…on the whole, as opposed to being admirable only with some
qualification” (Greenspan 60).
Emmanuel
Levinas “Ethics and Infinity”
In the collection of conversations
titled Ethics and Infinity the
philosopher Emmanuel Levinas summarizes his various theories on the Other. The
Other is any other human being, but the knowledge and perception of the Other
lies in the face. Levinas concludes that “you turn yourself toward the Other as
toward an object” (85) but you do not achieve knowledge/perception of the Other
as a human until you encounter “a nose, eyes, a forehead, a chin” (Levinas 85).
In other words, the humanity of the Other lies in the face.
Once the Other’s humanity is
encountered through the face, an ethical responsibility towards the Other
unfolds. By looking at the face of the Other an ethic duty arises in which “the
relation toward the face is straightaway ethical” (Levinas 87). By this Levinas means that once we have
encountered the face a requirement towards responsibility ensues, a
responsibility to not kill. Because of the humanity behind the face of the
Other Levinas insists that the “face is what one cannot kill” (87). This is the
ethical responsibility behind the face, once we have encountered the face of
the Other we cannot kill it, based on our mutual humanity and
knowledge/perception of this humanity.
Levinas overall theoretical
framework behind the Other is extremely complex, especially as it relates to
overall justice. If we take the axiom “Thou shalt not kill” as valid, then
Levinas argues that justice ensues from this axiom when multiplied. The face of
the Other commands the axiom “Thou shalt not kill” as an order (89) and this
command ensues when the Other is next to you. Multiplied this axiom many times
over to cover all of humanity, and this command, “Thou shalt not kill”, becomes
justice. Levinas insists that the “multiplicity of men and the presence of
someone else next to the Other. . .condition[s] [our] laws and establish[es]
justice” (89). The ethical responsibility to not kill the Other when multiplied
manifold over humanity creates justice. Ethics precedes justice.
Feodor
Dostoevsky, Crime and Punishment
Raskolnikov’s
dream of a murdered mare symbolizes the Nihilist movement and its theme of
utilizing violence to achieve social, political, and economic change, it is
also a metaphor for Raskolnikov’s inner psychology, which helps us understand
his reasoning for murdering Ivanovna, the pawn broker.
The Nihilist movement of 19th
century Russia centered on the concept that social, political, and economic
change cannot come about without the destruction of the current political and
social institutions. This movement accepted violence as not only morally right
but necessary. The central event of the Nihilist movement was the assassination
of Alexander II. Of course, violence for the sake of violence is never morally
right nor acceptable, and the dream of the dying mare illustrates the morally
objectionable action of the Nihilist.
In the scene, the horse gets whipped
and eventually murdered for no particular reason other than for the drunken
enjoyment of the crowd. From a psychological perspective, the dream symbolizes
Raskolnikov’s bipolarity towards violence and his society. By bipolarity, I
mean his contempt toward violence in his society (evident in the dream), his
use of violence (by killing pawnbroker), and his defense of violence (by
writing his essay later in the novel). In the dream, Raskolnikov interferes
with the violence going on and even gets a whip landed on him: “one of the
whips stung his face, but he did not feel it; he was wringing his hands and
crying aloud” (Dostoevsky 49). Even though in the dream he is a child, he
consciously objects to the violence perpetrated by the group. This act symbolizes his perversion towards
his society and their acceptance of violence. He seems broken hearted that the
horse is being whipped mercilessly with no concern for her well-being. The
crowd is drunk with both liquor and with the madness of violence. He interferes
because he rejects the violence, but at the same time, he accepts and defends
the ideology behind the violence.
Right after Raskolnikov wakes up from
the dream, he immediately starts thinking about the crime and if he should go
through with it. He starts to psycho-analyze himself and his dream: “I must
have realized that I should never carry it out, so why have I gone on
tormenting myself until now?” (Dostoevsky 51). But his bipolarity toward
violence comes through and the irony lies in the fact that he actually goes
through with the murder of the pawnbroker a couple of pages after this event.
As the novel goes on, he convinces himself that his violent act will have
positive consequences for his society. But he does not realize the perversion
behind his reasoning. Raskolnikov gets so caught up in his own mind and ideas
that he loses sight of who he is, his morality, and his humanity. His article,
“On Crime,” focuses on his Napoleonic ideas and justification of violence.